1. The
novelty of the issue
This
article deals with the vexatious question of how to conceptualise the
human person as a living subject (i.e. having an existence, meaning ex-sistere:
to be out), from the viewpoint of the social sciences broadly understood,
by commenting upon Margaret Archer’s recent book on the “internal
conversation” (Archer, 2003). The main difficulty does not consist in seeing what
a human person is made of (i.e. the unity of body and mind, the continuity
of a “substance” together with its “accidents”, etc.), but what relates
the single components of the human person (their properties and powers) to
themselves and to the external world.
Archer
deliberately starts the story from the Enlightenment. Why does she do so?
Why not to start from previous eras, as scholars often do, particularly
when trying to define the human person? The answer is trivial, but it
deserves to be explained: the answer is that the social sciences she is
talking about have been born with modernity. The attempt to tackle the
issue by going back to previous conceptualisations would be vain. This is
so for two main reasons.
i) The
issue, as Archer proposes it has not been “thematised” (understood as a
theme in itself) before the modern epoch. In other words, “the social
dimensions” of the human person in his/her inner and outer life do not
represent a meaningful and central issue per se in pre-modern
thought, from ancient Greece to the Middle Age. So much so that, if we try
to understand the social dimensions of the human person by relying upon
the classical philosophical categories, we come across “natural
explanations” which cannot grasp the reality we are trying to explain.
ii) The
challenges issued by modern and post-modern society to the very existence
of the human person have no precedent in the history. These challenges are
so great and radical that they require the elaboration of a new paradigm,
based on a social ontology able to comprehend the empirical evidences as
offered by the social sciences. For the first time in history, our society
describes itself as non-human, and even anti-human, in deeply conscious
and convincing ways.
To put
it bluntly, the issue of understanding the human person from the viewpoint
of the social sciences can certainly resort to the wisdom and knowledge of
the classical thought, but cannot find a solution within it. The basic
reason for that is that modernity has generated the issue of the social
relationality inherent in the human person on the basis of modalities,
which did not exist before the explosion of modernity. The unity of the
human person has been submitted to processes of differentiation in every
dimension. The relations between the differentiated dimensions (what one
calls today “the process of individualisation of the individual”) cannot
be approached by applying to pre-modern knowledge categories.
In
which way and to what extent this situation implies a revision of
classical metaphysics is a topic that has been largely perceived, but
certainly not solved. The revision should take into account the fact that
classical metaphysics deals with the human person within the general
ontology of entia, while the modern turn implies a distinct
ontology of the human person as different from the other entia
(Polo, 1991, 1993). The issue put forward by Archer appeals to an ontology
of “the social” which is still to be fully developed.
Classical philosophy has conceived of the social as a pure “accident”,
which can be separated from the substance or nature of the ens (Fabro,
2004). If we conceptualise the “sociability” of the human person as “relationality”
which is “constitutive” of him/her, we must go further than the
distinction between substance and accident. We must treat the relational
character (natural, practical, social and spiritual) of the human person
as co-essential to his/her existence and to our understanding.
Archer
responds to the challenge. She does so in an original way, in a
distinctive way in respect to almost all those thinkers who have dealt
with the same issue, for instance M. Buber and M. Heidegger and, as
concerns sociology, the various schools which go back to the classics
(Durkheim, Weber, Pareto and Simmel). They are rightly put under the
headings of reductionist and conflationary theories.
2.
Archer’s thesis about the shortcoming of modernity in dealing with the
human person and the need for a new perspective
Archer
maintains that modernity has brought about an issue, the relational
constitution of the human person, while treating it on the basis of
distorted approaches, which cannot account for what really generates and
regenerates the human person. In her opinion, the sociological problem of
conceptualising the person is how to capture someone who is both partly
formed by their sociality, but also has the capacity to transform their
society in some part. The difficulty is that social theorising has
oscillated between these two extremes. On the one hand, Enlightenment
thought promoted an “undersocialised” view of man, one whose human
constitution owed nothing to society and was thus a self-sufficient
“outsider” who simply operated in a social environment. On the other hand,
there is a later but pervasive “oversocialised” view of man, whose every
feature, beyond his biology, is shaped and moulded by his social context.
He thus becomes such a dependent “insider” that he has no capacity to
transform his social environment.
Archer
points out that modernity is intrinsically unbalanced: it sees only the
over-socialisation and the under-socialisation of the human person. The
well-known distinction between homo sociologicus and homo
oeconomicus is based on these reductions.
Archer
claims that the dilemma lies in the circular loop which links the person
to society: the person is “both ‘child’ and ‘parent’ of society”, the
generated and the generator at the same time. We need a new scientific
paradigm to understand how the human person can be both (a) dependent on
society (a supine social product) and (b) autonomous and possessing its
own powers (a self-sufficient maker). Classical philosophical thought has
coped with this dilemma in a quite simple way: it has reduced the
dependence on society to contingency and it has treated autonomy by means
of the concept of substance. A “solution” which refers to a low-complex
and “non-relational” society.
The
idea of classical philosophy, according to which the person is a substance
and society is an accidental reality, cannot be sustained any longer if we
want to understand the vicissitudes and the destiny of the post-modern
man. After modernity, it is not possible to understand social relations
basically as a projection of the human person.
Differently from classical thought, which denies the paradox inherent in
the sociality of man, modernity accepts it and, more than that, it
generates it. But the question is: how does modernity solve the paradox,
granting that it tries to solve it?
Archer
claims that modernity looks for possible solutions by adopting
conflationary epistemologies. And by this way modern social sciences lose
the human person as such. She is undoubtedly right. So we are left
with the task of “rescuing” the singularity of each human person, his/her
dignity and irreducibility, and, at the same time, of seeing the
embodiment and embeddedness of the person in social reality without
confusing or separating the two faces (singularity and sociality). How can
this task be accomplished?
Archer
proposes a better conception of man, from the perspective of social
realism, which grants humankind (i) temporal priority, (ii) relative
autonomy, and (iii) causal efficacy, in relation to the social beings that
they become and the powers of transformative reflection and action which
they bring to their social context, powers that are independent of social
mediation.
These
three operations (i, ii, iii) – as seen from the viewpoint of the social
realism - are not easy to be understood where one wishes to avoid a
desocialised vision of the human person. As a matter of fact, Archer’s
proposal is to open a new perspective (a relational perspective) on the
processes of human socialisation. The novelty lies in prompting that there
is a temporal priority of the person vis-à-vis society (which is
counter-intuitive), in conceiving of autonomy as experience guided by an
internal conversation and by understanding the concept of ‘relative’ as
‘relational’, and by restoring the notion of causality.
These
operations become likely within a theory that, going well beyond modern
social sciences, states that:
-
reality is stratified: whichever kind of reality we are observing, it
is made up with multiple layers, each one possessing its own powers and
emergent properties;
- in
between the layers, there exists a temporal relationality,
which means that powers and properties are emergent effects;
- all
in all, the relationality of the human person is conceivable as a
morphostatic/morphogenetic process.
By
adopting this social theory, based upon a realist epistemology (which is
called critical, analytical, and relational, without being relationist),
it becomes possible to perform some operations which otherwise would be
impossible.
1) We
can see the pre-social and meta-social reality of the human
person, so that the human person cannot be reduced neither to a social
product (conflated with society) nor to an idealistic concept;
2) We
can observe the identity of the self, its continuity and its ability to
mature within and through social interactions, while displaying between
nature and the ultimate concerns.
3) We
can see how the singularity of the human person is realised in a unique
and necessary combination of four orders of reality (natural, practical,
social, spiritual or supernatural), so that the contingency turns into a
necessity if the person must personalise his/herself and thus becoming
‘more’ human.
The
challenge of the widespread argument about “the individualisation of the
individual” is turned into the argument of “the personalisation of the
person”.
3. Why
an after-modern paradigm?
The
sweeping criticism of the modern social sciences worked out by Archer
(what she calls the two complementary faces of Modernity’s Man and
Society’s being) is intended to overcome the modernism itself as a
mentality and as an obsolete scientific paradigm. That’s why I believe
that Archer is developing an after-modern way of theorising about
social reality, and consequently about the human person.
She is
able to show, in a clear and well argued way, how the two main strands of
modern social sciences are now conflating in a particular version (the
central conflation between agency and structure) - which can be also
called the lib/lab conflation - where the human person and the
surrounding society are mutually interacting and generating each other
without the chance to distinguish between different contributions,
properties, powers and the temporal phases of the processes.
As I
have already said, Archer rejects all forms of conflationary thought by
elaborating the paradigm of morphogenesis/morphostasis, based upon a
social ontology in which the human person recovers his/her priority both
logical and temporal, but without getting into a metaphysical abstraction
or an idealist entity. I’d like to reformulate her view in the following
way. I suggest to criss-cross Archer’s scheme concerning the development
of the self (Archer, 2003) (1) with the AGIL scheme as revised in the relational
theory of society (Donati, 1991, 2006). (fig. 1).
The
human person is someone who, standing in between the natural world
(bio-physical) and transcendence, develops through social interaction. At
the start, the person is a subject or potential self (“I”) who, through
experience (practice), gets out of nature and becomes a primary agent
(“me”), then a corporate agent (“we”), then an actor (auctor)
(“you”). To me, it is at this point that the dialectic I/you meets the
need to cope with the transcendental world. Then the subject returns on to
the “I” as self. The “exit” from nature must always pass through the
nature again and again. The transcendental reality is treated in the
reflexive phase that the subject realises after having passed through
practice and sociality. Through these passages, the subject becomes a more
mature self-living in society.
Every
mode of being a self (as I, me, we, you) is a dialogue (an internal
conversation) with her own “I”. The battlefields are everywhere. But I’d
like to emphasise that they are particularly meaningful (i) at the borders
between the “I” and the bio-physical nature, (ii) in social interactions,
(iii) at the borders with the transcendental world (see fig. 1). Archer
discusses the third area in detail because this battlefield is the most
underestimated within the social sciences. She makes clear how the human
person can get a progressive divinisation (Theosis) while being in
the world. Figure 1 makes it explicit that the You can go out of the
social and come back to it without living the circle of practice and
experience of the world. That is why the personal identity (PI) emerges as
distinct from the social identity (SI) exactly because the former is in
constant interaction with the latter: but the latter (SI) is subordinated
(i.e. is a sub-set) to the former (PI).
Social
identity is the capacity to express what we care about in social roles
that are appropriate for doing this. Social identity comes from
adopting a role and personifying it in a singular manner, rather than
simply animating it. But here we meet a dilemma. It seems as though we
have to call upon personal identity to account for who does the
active personification. Yet, it also appears that we cannot make such an
appeal, for on this account it looks as though personal identity
cannot be attained before social identity is achieved. How
otherwise can people evaluate their social concerns against other kinds of
concerns when ordering their ultimate concerns? Conversely, it also seems
as if the achievement of social identity is dependent upon someone
having sufficient personal identity to personify any role in their
unique manner. This is the dilemma. The only way out of it is to accept
the existence of a dialectical relationship between personal and
social identities. Yet if this is to be more than fudging, then it is
necessary to venture three “moments” of the interplay (PI<-->SI) which
culminate in a synthesis such that both personal and social identities
are emergent and distinct, although they contributed to one another's
emergence and distinctiveness. By allowing that we need a person to do
the active personifying, it finally has to be conceded that our personal
identities are not reducible to being gifts of society. Unless
personal identity is indeed allowed on these terms, then there is no way
in which strict social identity can be achieved. In the process, our
social identity also becomes defined, but necessarily as a sub-set of
personal identity.
Society
is surely a contingent reality, but contingency does not mean pure
accident. It is in fact the notion of contingency which is in need for new
semantics. Contingency can mean “dependency on” (T. Parsons), or “the
chance not to be, and therefore to be potentially always otherwise” (N.
Luhmann), but it can also mean “the need for personal identity to mature
through social identity”. The third position implies that contingency can
be monitored by the ‘sense of self’, and guided through the internal
conversation of the subject.
Without
this different semantics of contingency, the human person could not take
the steps, which are necessary to go from nature to the supernatural
world, discovering its transcendence in respect to society. This is the
deepest sense of reflexivity as the proper operation of that “internal
conversation” which makes the human person more human. The social
relationality is precisely the fuel or food for the reflexivity, which
makes the human person effective.

Fig. 1 - The conceptualisation of the
human person as someone who develops in between nature, practice, social
interaction and transcendence
If we
apply the AGIL scheme (in the revised, relational version I have offered
in the book “Teoria relazionale della società”: Donati, 1991) to
the sequence I-me-we-you, we can see a quite curious thing: the natural
world occupies the dimension (function) of latency, while the
transcendental world occupies the dimension (function) of adaptation. Why
so? My interpretation is that the self is a latent reality rooted in its
nature, while the means which realise the human person as such do not
consist of material instruments, nor of practices as such, not to mention
the processes of socialisation due to the contrainte sociale, but
consist of its ultimate concerns. From this perspective we can
better understand the meaning of Archer’s statement according to which
“who we are is what we care about“: it means that our self becomes
what it generates in the “I” by way of adaptation to (confrontation with)
the ultimate concerns during the life span.
This
internal work (reflexivity) must be accomplished in the dialogue that the
“I” has with itself, i.e. when the “I” asks who is really its own “I” when
confronted with a Me, a We (fellowship) and a You (one who play a social
role in which ultimate concerns are involved). To operate the distinction,
“the ‘I’ of my ‘I’” does not mean to be self-referential by re-entering
the same distinction (as Luhman thinks): it is also, and at the same time,
to choose which environment to refer to (and therefore it is also an etero-referential
operation, but accomplished by the same identical person). When discussing
with his/herself and deciding where to bring the “I”, one self has to be
both self-referent and etero-referent (this is where “the social” comes
into play).
In
order to understand the process of humanisation of the person, it is
necessary to disprove the epistemic fallacy according to which “what
reality is taken to be, courtesy of our instrumental rationality or social
discourse, is substituted for reality itself” (Archer). In other words, in
order to arrive at a scientific model able to avoid any conflation in the
understanding of the human person as a relational being, it is necessary
to refute what is known today as epistemological “constructionism”, be it
radical or moderate. This can be done by using what I’d like to call the
epistemic triangle suggested by critical realism (fig. 2)

Fig. 2 - The epistemic triangle of
critical realism
As a
matter of fact, most contemporary social sciences claim that: i) the human
person can be known only as a product of knowledge (the person is viewed
as a cultural production of socialisation), meaning that the knower can
only know through the cultural products of the context he lives in; ii)
the relation between knowledge and known is supposed to be relativistic;
iii) the experienced relation of the knower towards the known is reified
(Pierre Bourdieu gives us an excellent example).
Archer
is able not only to criticise all these assumptions, but also to clearly
show how, behind the methodological and epistemological debate, lies an
“ontological issue”. What we are used to call methodological individualism
and methodological holism harbour opposite ontologies that she calls
anthropocentricism and sociocentricism. Only the epistemic triangle can
overcome this fallacies, in so far as it allows us (i) to distinguish
between knower, known and knowledge as stratified realities of different
orders, (ii) to consider their relations as reflexivity driven (instead of
being reified) (fig. 2).
In
Archer’s conceptual framework, personal knowledge is the product of a
complex series of operations, done by the self, through a reflexive
activity in relation to the reality to be known, in which the knowledge
already existing in society (its ‘culture’) is only a given (in systemic
terms: an environment).
Only
this epistemic triangle can valorise the human person as subject and
object of his/her own activity.
4. A
few questions
The
work by Archer offers many suggestions, which should be treated more
properly and more deeply than I can do here. Let me just raise some
questions.
With
reference to my figure 1, we can envisage the following open issues. They
lie a) at the borders between nature and the person in society, b) in the
relationships between the internal reflexivity of the person and its
social networks, c) at the boundaries between the human person and
transcendence.
a) The
border between nature and the person in society (the battlefield of
practical experience) becomes more and more problematic in so far as
society changes nature continuously. Certainly nature reacts. But changes
produced by science and technology are challenging the ability of the
human person to dialogue with nature in its very roots. The question is:
is/will the subject be able to relate itself to nature when society has
made/shall make nature more and more unrecognizable, or fuzzier and
fuzzier? It is evident that changes in the natural world can shift the
thresholds within which the experience of the ‘sense of self’ can be
adequately managed.
b) The
second question concerns the relation between the internal reflexivity of
the person and the social networks he/she belongs to.
The core claim of Archer’s argument is that consciousness should be
understood as emergent, where emergence implies the non-reducibility of
analysis; the epistemological impossibility of the reduction of the
emergent state is determined by the constitutive feature of consciousness,
namely, reflexivity. I agree on that. But, possibly, the
emphasis on the internal reflexivity needs to be connected to the
properties and powers of the social networks in which people live, given
that these networks may have their own “reflexivity” (of a different
kind).
c) The
third set of questions concerns the borders between the person and the
transcendental world. The ability of the human person to connect
him/herself to the transcendental world strongly depends on his/her
ability to “symbolize”, i.e. to understand and appropriate the symbolic
world (to know reality through symbols). The question is: how is this
ability produced in the internal conversation? How is it promoted or
endangered by society? Certainly we must distinguish between different
types of symbols: prelinguistic, linguistic and “appresentative” (in the
Luhmannian sense). But it seems to me that much effort should be made in
understanding the importance of symbols - their formation and their use –
to get a person properly involved in the supernatural. My feeling is that
sociology has reduced the symbols to what sociologists call the “media”
(the generalised media of interchange according to Parsons and the
generalised means of communication according to Luhmann). It is evident
that symbols cannot be reduced to ‘means’ when dealing with the
transcendental world. There is the need to better understand the role of
symbols in Archer’s framework.
To
conclude
The
emergentist paradigm worked out by Archer in order to understand the human
person puts the old query of the relation between personal identity and
social identity in new terms. I have used the word after-modern to
catch it.
Within
the social sciences, the relation Personal Identity
ßà
Social Identity is usually observed as an antithesis by. But it is clearly
not an antithesis. It is an interactive elaboration, which develops over
time, provided that the personal identity side operates it. It can induce
humanisation only by being asymmetric.
We can
therefore go well beyond those scholars who, in the last century, have
thought of the relation between Personal Identity and Social Identity as
something necessarily reifying the person (neo-marxists) or conceiving it
in dualistic terms (for instance Buber, but also Habermas and many
others). The human person must deal with all kinds of social relations. We
need not to oppose system relations and lifeworld relations, good and bad
relations “in themselves”, or warm and cold relations as Toennies referred
to, in so far as what is relevant is the reflexivity of the human
person in dealing with them.
Only
this vision can explain why and how the human person can emerge from
social interactions, while he/she precedes and goes beyond society. In
short, the relation between PI and SI is a dialogue between the lifeworld
(intersubjective relations) and social institutions (role relations), but
it must not be conceived as symmetric, because it is acted by the subject
(agent and actor) who does not want simply to animate a role, but also to
personify it in a singular manner.
Archer’s vision has positive implications in the long run: her critical
realism allows us to give room to, to think of and to promote the
capabilities of the human person to forge a more human society,
notwithstanding the fact that modernity has brought us into an anti-human
era. That’s why I have tried to comment on her book, by saying that the
“economy” of the human beings does not lie on their natural, physical or
material means, but on what fuels their ultimate concerns.
Bibliographic references
Archer, M.S. (2003). Structure, agency and the
internal conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Donati, P. (1991). Teoria relazionale della società. Milano:
Franco Angeli.
Donati, P. (Ed.) (2006). Sociologia: un’introduzione allo studio
della società. Padova: Cedam.
Fabro,
C. (2004).
Dall’essere all’esistente:
Hegel,
Kierkegaard, Heidegger e
Jaspers.
Genova: Marietti.
Polo, L. (1991). Quién es el hombre: un espiritu en el mundo.
Madrid: Ed. Rialp.
Polo, L. (1993). Presente y futuro del hombre. Madrid: Ed.
Rialp.
Note
(1)
See
Archer, 2003,
pp. 123-129. [volta]
Note on the author
Pierpaolo Donati is
the founder of relational sociology. He is a professor of sociology at
University of Bologna´s College of Political Sciences and also director of
the Social Politics and Sanitary Sociology Study Center of that university.
Author of more than 500 publications, in Italian and other idioms, Donati
was president of the Italian Sociology Association. Contact: donati@spbo.unibo.it
Data
de recebimento: 19/06/2005
Data de aceite: 30/10/2006
-
-
Memorandum 11, out/2006
Belo Horizonte: UFMG; Ribeirão Preto: USP
-
ISSN 1676-1669
-
http://www.fafich.ufmg.br/~memorandum/a11/donati01.htm